Uncertainty and the history of ideas

Adrian Blau

Research output: Contribution to journalArticlepeer-review

317 Downloads (Pure)

Abstract

Intellectual historians often make empirical claims, but can never know for certain if these claims are right. Uncertainty is thus inevitable for intellectual historians. But accepting uncertainty is not enough: we should also act on it, by trying to reduce and report it. We can reduce uncertainty by amassing valid data from different sources to weigh the strengths and weaknesses of competing explanations, rather than trying to "prove" an empirical claim by looking for evidence that fits it. Then we should report our degree of certainty in our claims. When we answer empirical questions in intellectual history, we are not telling our readers what happened: we are telling them how strong we think our evidence isâ€"a crucial shift of emphasis. For intellectual historians, then, uncertainty is subjective, as discussed by Keynes and Collingwood; the paper thus explores three differences between subjective and objective uncertainty. Having outlined the theoretical basis of uncertainty, the paper then offers examples from actual research: Noel Malcolm's work shows how to reduce and report uncertainty about composition, and David Wootton's work shows how to reduce and report uncertainty about beliefs. © 2011 Wesleyan University.
Original languageEnglish
Pages (from-to)358-372
Number of pages14
JournalHistory and Theory
Volume50
Issue number3
DOIs
Publication statusPublished - Oct 2011

Keywords

  • Collingwood
  • history of ideas
  • history of political thought
  • interpretation
  • methodology
  • Quentin Skinner
  • uncertainty

Fingerprint

Dive into the research topics of 'Uncertainty and the history of ideas'. Together they form a unique fingerprint.

Cite this